Consciousness is a Form of Life, #4–Dynamic Emergence, Life, and Consciousness.

Mr Nemo
19 min readJan 11, 2021

--

By Robert Hanna

“The Sower,” by Vincent Van Gogh (1888/1889)

***

TABLE OF CONTENTS

I. Introduction

II. Conscious-Mind-is-a-Form-of-Life 1: Solving The Mind-Body Problem

III. Dynamic Systems Theory and The Dynamic World Picture

IV. Conscious-Mind-is-a-Form-of-Life 2: Solving The Free Will Problem

V. Dynamic Emergence, Life, and Consciousness

VI. Conclusion

***

This final installment contains sections V and VI.

But you can also download or read a .pdf of the complete version of this essay HERE.

***

V. Dynamic Emergence, Life, and Consciousness

By emergence, in general, I mean the process whereby a categorically simpler (less complex, more superficial) old structure or system S1 evolves — opens up and unfolds — into a categorically richer (more complex, deeper-rooted) new structure or system S2, such that S2 makes explicit what was previously only implicit in S1. For example, human social institutions emerge from human mindedness; human mindedness emerges from complex organismic life; complex organismic life emerges from unicellular organismic life; and unicellular organismic life emerges from non-equilibrium thermodynamic energy flows exemplifying classical quantum properties or states such as the particle/wave duality, complementarity, entanglement, and non-locality.

This definition of emergence — in terms of processes whereby structures or systems evolve from older, simpler, less complex and more superficial global properties or states, into essentially newer, more complex, and deeper-rooted global properties or states of that structure or system, thereby making explicit what was previously only implicit in the earlier states — is sharply distinct from standard definitions of emergence in terms of a synchronic and time-reversible strong supervenience relation between qualitative or relational properties or states of parts, and distinct qualitative or relational global properties or states of wholes. Indeed, if I’m correct about this, then the former kind of emergence is metaphysically genuine emergence, and the latter kind of emergence is merely a metaphysically phony emergence, i.e., nothing but a metaphysical myth. Let me explain.

For clarity’s sake, and in order for what follows in this section to make sense to readers who don’t closely follow the (to be frank, highly Scholastic, and often trivial) debates in recent or contemporary Analytic metaphysics, I’ll define a metaphysical relation called strong supervenience.

Strong supervenience[i] is a necessary determination-relation between sets of properties or states of different ontological “levels,” a relation that is weaker than strict property/state-identity, and is usually taken to be asymmetric, although two-way or bilateral supervenience is also possible. But assuming for the purposes of simpler exposition that strong supervenience is asymmetric, then, more precisely, B-properties/states (= the higher level properties/states) strongly supervene on A-properties/states (= the lower-level properties/states) if and only if

(i) for any property/state F among the A-properties/states had by something X, F necessitates X’s also having property/state G among the B-properties/states (upwards necessitation), and

(ii) there cannot be a change in any of X’s B-properties/states without a corresponding change in X’s A-properties/states (necessary co-variation).

It follows from strong supervenience that any two things X and Y share all their A-properties/states in common only if they share all their B-properties/states in common (indiscriminability).

In turn, logical supervenience is a super-strong version of strong supervenience which says that the necessitation relations between the B-properties/states and the A-properties/states are logical and a priori. Or more simply put: The B-properties/states are “nothing more than” and “nothing over and above” the A-properties/states. If logical supervenience holds, then if there were such a being as an all-powerful and all-knowing creator God, and if They were to create and/or know all the A-properties/states, then They would have nothing more to do in order to create and/or know all the B-properties/states. By contrast to logical supervenience, nomological or natural strong supervenience is a modally weaker notion which says that the the necessitation relations between the B-properties/states and the A-properties/states are determined by laws of nature, and hold in all and only the worlds in which those natural laws obtain.

It’s crucial to recognize that no matter what its level of modal strength, strong supervenience specifies at best a set of extrinsic modal properties and relations (namely, upwards necessitation, necessary co-variation, and indiscriminability) between a thing’s A-properties/states and its B-properties/states, or between any two things’ A-properties/states and B-properties/states. If relations of strong supervenience hold for a thing or things, as such, then there is no further implication that these are relations of constitution, essence, or efficacious causal power, such that a thing’s or things’ immanent structural characteristics — and in particular, if the thing or things are natural or physical, their efficacious causal powers — depend on these relations. Conversely, if relations of constitution, essence, or causal efficacy hold for a thing or things, then there is no further implication that strong supervenience holds for them. In short, the metaphysics of strong supervenience is modally shallow, not modally deep, unlike the real metaphysics of manifestly real constitution, essence, or causality.[ii]

Correspondingly, as Jaegwon Kim repeatedly pointed out,[iii] the fundamental metaphysical flaw in the notion of strong supervenience is that, given the modal shallowness of the strong supervenience relation, the possession of a set of efficacious causal powers by the supervenience base inherently rules out and undermines — excludes — the transmission of those efficacious causal powers to the supervening properties/states, thereby rendering the supervening properties/states epiphenomenal and causally inert. Hence this is known as The Causal Exclusion Problem.

Now back to emergence. The concept of emergence has its historical source in early 20th century debates about scientific reductionism, and in particular the mechanism vs. vitalism controversy in the philosophy of biology.[iv] Eventually, that controversy withered away — no doubt because by the end of the 1950s, scientific naturalism (including the sub-doctrines of scientism, natural mechanism, and reductive materialism or physicalism), was the conventional wisdom in mainstream Analytic philosophy.[v] In the late 1990s and early 2000s however, the concept of emergence (as it were) re-emerged in the context of the mind-body problem and more specifically in the context of the problem of mental causation.[vii]

Very simply put, the general doctrine of emergence says that irreducibly new global properties or states of a formal or natural system can come out of old properties or states of that formal or natural system. In other and even fewer words, emergence is formal or natural creativity.

For the time being, and for simplicity’s sake, let’s concentrate on emergence as it applies to natural systems, all of which are dynamic systems in space and time. Later in this section, I’ll briefly come back to emergence as it applies to formal systems — which I’ll call constructive emergence — in order to present an illuminating analogy with its application to dynamic systems.

In any case, it should be immediately noticed, however, that the contrast between the newness versus the oldness of the properties of a natural system is ambiguous as between whether it should be understood as the contrast between, on the one hand, (a) the less ontologically basic properties or states of a natural system vs. the more ontologically basic properties or states of that system (for example, the system’s temperature vs. its mean molecular motion, or the system’s being water vs. its being H2O), or whether on the other hand it should be understood as the contrast between

(b) those properties or states of a natural system whose instances exist earlier in time vs. those properties or states of that system whose instances exist only later in time (for example, the system’s being a build-up of towering cumulus clouds vs. its later being a thunderstorm, or the system’s acorn-ness vs. its later oak tree-ness).

Correspondingly, the notion of coming out of is ambiguous as to whether it should be understood as, on the one hand, (a∗) the simultaneous strong supervenience of various global properties or states of the natural system on the non-relational or relational properties of its local proper parts (for example, the strong supervenience of the system’s temperature at any given time on its mean molecular motion at that same time, or the strong supervenience of the system’s being water on its being H2O), or whether on the other hand it should be understood as (b∗) the evolution of various global properties or states of the system only over time (for example, the growth of a thunderstorm out of a build-up of towering cumulus clouds, or the growth of an oak tree out of an acorn).

Noting these conceptual ambiguities is extremely important, because the pair consisting of (a) and (b), and the pair consisting of (a∗) and (b∗), while they may seem superficially consistent with each other, are in fact inconsistent. This becomes clearer when we formulate the notions corresponding to each pair more explicitly. The conceptual pair consisting of (a) and (a∗) is what I’ll call essentially synchronic and supervenient emergence, aka static emergence, aka phony emergence, and the conceptual pair consisting of (b) and (b∗) is what I’ll call essentially diachronic and non-supervenient emergence, aka dynamic emergence, aka genuine emergence.

The paradigm of essentially synchronic and supervenient emergence, aka static emergence, aka phony emergence, is what Kim aptly called mereological supervenience,[7] whereby the global properties of a natural system, supposedly, locally strongly supervene on its compositional atoms; whereas the paradigm of essentially diachronic and non-supervenient emergence, aka dynamic emergence, aka genuine emergence, is natural growth. Therefore it should be already obvious that whereas the concept of static emergence is an inherently mechanist notion, the concept of dynamic emergence is an inherently organicist notion.

Or otherwise put, the concept of static emergence is how the mechanistic worldview “murders to dissect” and tries to turn natural growth into its dialectical contrary.

Essentially Synchronic and Supervenient Emergence, aka Static Emergence, aka Phony Emergence

A natural system (supposedly[viii]) has essentially synchronic emergent properties or states if and only if new properties or states of that system come out of old properties or states of that system such that

(i) necessarily, the new properties or states of that system occur at a less ontologically basic level than the old properties or states (for example, the system’s temperature vs. its mean molecular motion), and

(ii) necessarily, the new properties are global properties of the system that simultaneously locally strongly supervene on the non-relational or relational properties of its local proper parts (for example, the local strong supervenience of the system’s temperature at any given time on its mean molecular motion at that same time, or the local strong supervenience of the system’s being water at any given time on its being H2O at that same time).

More generally then, the doctrine of static emergence (mistakenly) says four things.

First, nature contains physical wholes, or systems, whose local proper parts relationally interact over time in a way that yields novel global properties of these systems.

Second, these novel global properties cannot be predicted from scientific knowledge of the proper parts alone.

Third, nevertheless these novel global properties do locally strongly supervene on the local intrinsic, non-relational fundamental physical properties of their proper parts, together with the extrinsic relational properties of those proper parts, and are not identical with any of those properties.

Fourth and finally, this local strong supervenience is only accidentally diachronic, and time-reversible (symmetrical with respect to its temporal direction), hence essentially synchronic.

Essentially Diachronic and Non-Supervenient Emergence, aka Dynamic Emergence, aka Genuine Emergence

A natural system has essentially diachronically emergent properties or states if and only if new properties of that system come out of old properties of that system such that

(i) necessarily, the new properties or states of that system are instantiated later than its old properties and do not exist in that system at any time prior to the existence of its old properties or states (for example, the system exemplifies being a thunderstorm later than it exemplifies being a build-up of towering cumulus clouds, and can never exemplify being a thunderstorm before it has exemplified being a build-up of towering cumulus clouds; or the system exemplifies oak tree-ness later than it exemplifies acornness, and can never exemplify oak-treeness before it has exemplified acorn-ness), and

(ii) necessarily, the new properties or states of the system evolve from older,simpler, less complex, and more superficial causally efficacious global properties or states, into essentially newer, more complex, and deeper-rooted causally efficacious global properties or states of that structure or system, by means of various causal interactions between the structure or system and its environment over thermodynamically irreversible time, thereby making explicit what was previously only implicit in the earlier properties or states (for example, the growth of a thunderstorm out of a build-up of towering cumulus clouds, or the growth of an oak tree out of an acorn).

More generally then, the doctrine of dynamic emergence (correctly) says four things.

First, nature contains physical processes, or systems, namely self-organizing thermodynamic systems, whose new properties or states evolve from older, simpler, less complex and more superficial causally efficacious global properties or states of that system, into essentially newer, more complex, and deeper-rooted causally efficacious global properties or states of that system, by means of various causal interactions between the system and its environment over thermodynamically irreversible time, thereby making explicit what was previously only implicit in the earlier properties or states.

Second, the novel and causally efficacious global properties or states of such systems cannot be predicted from scientific knowledge of the proper parts alone.

Third, these novel and causally efficacious global properties or states do not locally strongly supervene on the local intrinsic non-relational fundamental physical properties of all their proper parts, together with the extrinsic relational properties of those proper parts, and are not identical with any of those properties, nor do they globally strongly supervene on fundamental physical properties.

Fourth and finally, dynamic emergence is time-irreversible (asymmetrical with respect to its temporal direction), hence essentially diachronic.

Everyday examples of essentially diachronic and non-supervenient dynamic emergence include the non-organismic growth of thunderstorms out of build-ups of towering cumulus clouds, and the organismic growth of oak trees out of acorns. But there is also strong evidence for essentially diachronic and non-supervenient dynamic emergence from entangled quantum systems and quantum field theory.[ix] In entangled quantum systems, the newly resulting compound determines the original constituents (particles) rather than the other way around, as mereological supervenience would suggest. Quantum field theory strongly indicates that there is no ultimate level of ‘‘really real’’particles on which everything else is strongly supervenient.[x] Rather, quantum fields are patterns of process over time that exist in many different types of complexity. The phenomenon of spontaneous symmetry breaking[xi] likewise points to dynamic emergence. And there is also Bohm’s profound idea of quantum potential,[xii] a pilot-wave guiding the behavior of the particle. Therefore, contemporary particle physics and quantum mechanics, at least according to my dynamicist, organicist, and processualist take on the Bohmian interpretation,[xiii] strongly confirms the existence of dynamic emergence.

So, the basic metaphysical claim I am making in this section is that conscious mind, complex organismic life, and unicellular organismic life, all non-superveniently and causally efficaciously emerge in far-from-equilibrium, spatiotemporally asymmetric, complex, self-organizing thermodynamic systems, hence they are rightly regarded as paradigm examples of genuine emergence. And leaving aside the jargon of contemporary Analytic metaphysics now, my basic point is just this: conscious mind, complex organismic life, and unicellular organismic life, all arise in nature as temporally novel, immanent structural properties or states of natural processes possessing a certain suitable level of thermodynamic complexity. As immanent-structural, such features do not metaphysically pop out of these natural processes, at all, but even more specifically they do not metaphysically pop out at-a-time, or synchronically, since the thermodynamics of the processes themselves, in asymmetric time, is inherently and internally guided and self-determined by these very same structural features: on the contrary, they evolve. By this, I mean that one less complex state of far-from-equilibrium, spatiotemporally asymmetric, and complex, but still non-self-organizing or non-living thermodynamics (for example, the Belousov-Zhabotinsky chemical reaction, with or without a catalyst and light-excitation[xiv]) dynamically opens up and unfolds into another, essentially richer thermodynamic structure (for example, that of unicellular organismic life), just as the less complex system of the rational numbers constructively opens up and unfolds into the essentially richer system of the real numbers by means of, for example, Cantorian diagonalization, the power-set operation, or the Dedekind-cut operation; and constructive emergence in formal systems is also manifest when we move from the natural or whole numbers to the rational numbers, from sentential logic to classical predicate logic, from classical predicate logic to Principia Mathematica-style mathematical logic,[xv] or from classical logic to non-classical logic.[xvi]

“Opening up and unfolding into” is of course a metaphor. Nevertheless, I think that by means of an evocative image, it accurately conveys the core idea that the dynamic emergence is essentially inside the asymmetric spatiotemporal processes constituting its non-equilibrium thermodynamics, just as the real numbers are essentially between the rational numbers, and the rational numbers are essentially between the natural and whole numbers. Dynamic emergence, aka genuine emergence, then, is the spatiotemporally asymmetric self-revelation of, opening-and-unfolding-into, actualization of, or rendering explicit, a previously merely implicit and potential essentially richer thermodynamic structure, with correspondingly new efficacious causal powers. Confusing static emergence, aka phony emergence, with dynamic emergence, aka genuine emergence, is a paradigmatic example of what Whitehead aptly called the fallacy of misplaced concreteness: mistaking the abstract for the concrete.[xvii] But in this case, it’s also a paradigmatic example of mistaking a metaphysical myth for what is metaphysically real.

VI. Conclusion

Inspired by Whitehead’s brilliant insights into the nature of nature, although not restricted by his panexperientialist metaphysics, I’ve undertaken a radical re-thinking of our concept of nature by radically re-conceiving it as inherently processual and purposive, from The Big Bang Singularity forward to organismic life, and then to conscious mind, which in turn entailed radically re-conceiving the mind-body relation, free agency, and emergence, all of which are fully embedded inside The Dynamic World Picture. So I conclude that I’ve proved — or at least made a strong case for — the conscious-mind-is-a-form-of-life thesis: that there’s a single, unbroken metaphysical continuity between The Big Bang Singularity, organismic life, and conscious mind. I also think that, beyond recognizing the truth of the CMFL thesis, if we then manage to wrap our heads and hearts wholeheadedly and wholeheartedly around the philosophical, scientific, and sociocultural radical Gestalt shift that’s entailed and presupposed by this thesis, not only will it be, as it were, the Big Kahuna of all Kuhnian paradigm shifts,[xviii] but also radically change our lives for the better. That, however, is another and somewhat longer story for another day.[xix]

NOTES

[i] See, e.g., Kim, Supervenience and Mind, esp. part 1; Horgan, “From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World”; and Chalmers, The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory, chs. 1–3.

[ii] See Hanna, “Kant, the Copernican Devolution, and Real Metaphysics.”

[iii] See, e.g., Kim, Supervenience and Mind.

[iv] See Stephan, “Emergence: A Systematic View of its Historical Facets’’; and McLaughlin, “The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism.”

[v] See, e.g., Hanna and Paans, “This is the Way the World Ends: A Philosophy of Civilization Since 1900, and A Philosophy of the Future,” sections 2–3.

[vi] See, e.g., Beckermann et al., (eds.), Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism; and O’Connor, “Emergent Properties.”

[vii] See Kim, “Multiple Realizability and the Metaphysics of Reduction.”

[viii] Remember, I’m arguing for the idea that static emergence is nothing but a metaphysical myth; hence I don’t want to be taken even to imply that I think that there really is such a thing.

[ix] See, e.g., Silberstein and McGeever, ‘‘The Search For Ontological Emergence’’; and Stapp, Mind, Matter, and Quantum Mechanics.

[x] Bickhard and Campbell, “Emergence,” p. 331.

[xi] See, e.g., Brading, Castellani, and Teh, “Symmetry and Symmetry Breaking.”

[xii] See, e.g., Bohm and Hiley, “On the Intuitive Understanding of Nonlocality as Implied by Quantum Theory”; Bohm, Wholeness and the Implicate Order; and Bruntrup, “Is Psycho-Physical Emergentism Committed to Dualism? The Causal Efficacy of Emergent Mental Properties,” p. 147.

[xiii] See, e.g., Goldstein, “Bohmian Mechanics”; and also Hanna, THE END OF MECHANISM: A Neo-Organicist Novum Organum, section 15.

[xiv] See, e.g., Prigogine, The End of Certainty: Time’s Flow and the Laws of Nature, pp. 66–67; and Wikipedia, “The Belousov-Zhabotinsky Reaction.” The Belousov-Zhabotinsky reaction can be excited into self-organizing activity by means of the influence of light, using tris(bipyridine)ruthenium(II) chloride as a catalyst. But even this still falls short of organismic life.

[xv] Gödel’s incompleteness theorems — whose proofs deploy Gödel-numbering, Cantorian diagonalization, and the Liar Paradox — show that this is a radical step, essentially analogous to the constructive emergence of the real numbers from the rational numbers. See Gödel, “On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems.”

[xvi] See, e.g., Hanna, Rationality and Logic, esp. ch. 2.

[xvii] Whitehead, Science and the Modern World, p. 51.

[xviii] See Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.

[xix] See, e.g., Hanna and Paans, “This is the Way the World Ends: A Philosophy of Civilization Since 1900, and A Philosophy of the Future”; Torday, Miller Jr, and Hanna, “Singularity, Life, and Mind: New Wave Organicism”; and Hanna, THE END OF MECHANISM:A Neo-Organicist Novum Organum.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Beckermann, A. et al., (eds.), Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism. Berlin: De Gruyter, 1992.

Bickhard, M. and Campbell, D. “Emergence.” In P.B. Anderson et al. (eds.), Downward Causation (Denmark: Aarhus University Press, 2000. Pp. 322–348.

Bohm, D. Wholeness and the Implicate Order. New York: Routledge, 1982.

Bohm, D. and Hiley, B. “On the Intuitive Understanding of Nonlocality as Implied by Quantum Theory.” Foundations of Physics 5 (1975): 93–109.

Boolos, G. and Jeffrey, R. Computability and Logic. 3rd edn., Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1989.

Brading, K., Castellani, E., and Teh, N. “Symmetry and Symmetry Breaking.” In E.N. Zalta (ed.),The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). Available online at URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/symmetry-breaking/>.

Bruntrup, G. “Is Psycho-Physical Emergentism Committed to Dualism? The Causal Efficacy of Emergent Mental Properties.” Erkenntnis 48 (1998): 133–151.

Chalmers, D. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1996.

Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. “The Extended Mind.” Analysis 58 (1998): 7–19.

Gallagher, S. “The Overextended Mind.” Versus: Quaderni di studi semiotici (2011): 55–66.

Galison, P. Image and Logic: A Material Culture of Microphysics. Chicago, IL: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1997.

Gödel, K. “On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems.” In J. Van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 1967. Pp. 596–617.

Goldstein, S. “Bohmian Mechanics.” In E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). Available online at URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/qm-bohm/>.

Haken, H. Principles of Brain Functioning: A Synergetic Approach to Brain Activity, Behavior, and Cognition Berlin: Springer, 1996.

Hanna, R. Deep Freedom and Real Persons: A Study in Metaphysics (THE RATIONAL HUMAN CONDITION, Vol. 2). New York: Nova Science, 2018.

Hanna, R. THE END OF MECHANISM:A Neo-Organicist Novum Organum (Unpublished MS, 2020). Available online HERE.

Hanna, R. “Kant, the Copernican Devolution, and Real Metaphysics.” In M. Altman (ed.), Kant Handbook London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2017. Pp. 761–789.

Hanna, R. “Minding the Body.” Philosophical Topics 39 (2011): 15–40.

Hanna, R. Rationality and Logic. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006.

Hanna, R. and Maiese, M. Embodied Minds in Action. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2009.

Hanna, R. and Paans, O. “This is the Way the World Ends: A Philosophy of Civilization Since 1900, and A Philosophy of the Future,” Cosmos and History 16, 2 (2020): 1–53. Available online at URL = <http://cosmosandhistory.org/index.php/journal/article/viewFile/865/1510>.

Horgan, T. “From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World.” Mind 102 (1993): 555–586

Jantsch, E. The Self-Organizing Universe: Scientific and Human Implications of the Emerging Paradigm of Evolution. New York: Pergamon, 1980.

Kauffman, S. At Home in the Universe: The Search for Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1996.

Kauffman, S. The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1993.

Kim, J. “Multiple Realizability and the Metaphysics of Reduction.” In Kim, Supervenience and Mind. Pp. 309–335.

Kim, J. ‘‘The Non-Reductivist’s Troubles with Mental Causation.’’ In J. Kim, Supervenience and Mind. Pp. 336–357.

Kim, J. Supervenience and Mind. Cambridge MA: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1993.

Kuhn, T. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1962.

McLaughlin, B. “The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism.” In Beckermann et al. (eds)., Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism. Pp. 49–93.

Miller Jr., W.B., Torday, J.S., and Baluška, F., “Biological Evolution as the Defense of ‘Self’.” Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 142 (2019): 54–74.

Nicolis, G. and Prigogine, I. Self-Organization in Nonequilibrium Systems. New York: Wiley, 1977.

O’Connor, T. “Emergent Properties.” In E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition). Available online at URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/properties-emergent/>.

Prigogine, I. The End of Certainty: Time’s Flow and the Laws of Nature. New York: Free Press, 1997.

Royce, J. The Letters of Josiah Royce. Chicago, IL: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1970.

Schrödinger, E. What is Life? Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1944.

Silberstein, M. and McGeever, J. “The Search For Ontological Emergence.” Philosophical Quarterly 49 (1999): 182–200.

Stapp, H. Mind, Matter, and Quantum Mechanics. Munich: Springer, 1993.

Stephan, A. “Emergence: A Systematic View of its Historical Facets.” In A. Beckermann et al. (eds), Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism. Berlin: De Gruyter, 1992. Pp. 25–47.

Steward, H. A Metaphysics for Freedom. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2012.

Thompson, E. Mind in Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press, 2007.

Torday, J.S., Miller Jr, W.B., and Hanna, R., “Singularity, Life, and Mind: New Wave Organicism.” In J.S. Torday and W.B. Miller Jr, The Singularity of Nature: A Convergence of Biology, Chemistry and Physics Cambridge: Royal Society of Chemistry, 2020. Ch. 20. Pp. 206–246.

Turing, A. “On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem.” Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, series 2, 42 (1936): 230–265, with corrections in 43 (1937): 644–546.

Varela, F. Principles of Biological Autonomy. New York: Elsevier/North Holland, 1979.

Varela, F., Maturana, H., and Uribe, R. “Autopoiesis: The Organization of Living Systems, its Characterization and a Model.” Currents in Modern Biology 5 (1974): 187–196.

Weber, A. “Life.” In E.N. Zalta (ed.),The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition). Available online at URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/life/>.

Weber, A. and Varela, F. ‘‘Life After Kant: Natural Purposes and the Autopoietic Foundations of Biological Individuality.’’ Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1 (2002): 97–125.

Whitehead, A.N. The Concept of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1971/1920.

Whitehead, A.N. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology. Corrected edn., New York: The Free Press, 1978/1929.

Whitehead, A.N. Science and the Modern World. New York: The Free Press, 1967/1925.

Wikipedia. “The Belousov-Zhabotinsky Reaction” (2020). Available online at URL = <https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Belousov%E2%80%93Zhabotinsky_reaction>.

Wilson, M. The Invisible World: Early Modern Philosophy and the Invention of the Microscope. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press, 1995.

Wittgenstein, L. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans. C.K. Ogden. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981.

AGAINST PROFESSIONAL PHILOSOPHY REDUX 512

Mr Nemo, W, X, Y, & Z, Monday 11 January 2021

Against Professional Philosophy is a sub-project of the online mega-project Philosophy Without Borders, which is home-based on Patreon here.

Please consider becoming a patron!

--

--

Mr Nemo

Formerly Captain Nemo. A not-so-very-angry, but still unemployed, full-time philosopher-nobody.